Stephen Greenblatt’s The Swerve:
How the World Became Modern
I just
finished reading it. As a winner of a National Book Award and a Pulitzer Prize,
it has been conspicuously recognized as mega-worthy.1 Well, after
reading it, I agree with that judgment: it’s a very good book, engagingly
written. I do have a couple of criticisms, one of commission and another of
omission. I’ll explain briefly, but I want to make it clear that these remarks
should discourage no one from reading The
Swerve.
Swerving is what atoms do in Lucretius’s Latin poem that expands on the
picture of the world put forward by the Greek writings of Epicurus two and a half centuries earlier;2
only fragments survive of Epicurus’s works. The world, to say a sentence about Lucretius, and everything in it is made up of atoms and their swerving consists of
the unpredictable motions they make. The main character of the narrative is
Poggio, a passionate book hunter, living in the 15th century,
digging up ancient manuscripts in libraries, mostly of them belonging to
monasteries. It is he who finds De rerum
natura and copies it in the beautiful script for which he was known.
Poggio’s career is the continuo that holds the book together. In my
view, however, that did not call for an elaborate depiction of the
establishment of the Vatican, where Poggio was for a time employed, with
downright lurid passages about the corruptions of its denizens. I see those
passages as a come-on for readers not so interested in the main themes of the
book. As I see it, those
“entertaining” pages are an unnecessary diversion.
My
second critique might be considered a “professional” reaction of a long-retired
professor of philosophy. Greenblatt’s depiction of the way in which Lucretius’s
worldview is “modern,” is to contrast it to the beliefs as to what the world is
like at the time of the poem’s “discovery”—in the 15th century, with
a few references to somewhat later thinkers.
Most of
the differences that are spelled out between the world of Lucretius and that of
Poggio focus on Christian doctrine or, more specifically, Catholic beliefs at
the time just before the Protestant reformation. Lucretius’ atomism will have
nothing to do with a separation of body and soul, with the latter living after
the death of the flesh. But not only the afterlife, basic to Christianity, is
denied, but the conceptions of sin and guilt are wholly undermined. Finally—one
might say “last but not least”—On the
Nature of Things depicts a universe that is, for practical purposes,
without God. That’s not quite true, since Lucretius states that there indeed are gods but that they have nothing to
do with us or with the world we live in.
It’s a kind of backhanded lip service to conventional beliefs.
Now the
world that Lucretius rejects, to come to my quasi-professorial comment, is not
only depicted in the Christian doctrine that Greenblatt discusses. The atomism,
rooted in Epicurus, is also radically distinct from the world that Aristotle
depicts and that is adapted to Christianity by Thomas Aquinas (1215-1274) who
lived and worked well before Poggio rediscovered Lucretius’ hymn to a world so
radically different. Without trying to give an account of this “predecessor” of
a world consisting entirely of undifferentiated atoms, let me simply say that
this “older” world consists of
countless substances each of which has its own characteristics, related
to each other by a great variety of bonds that create a world that one might
say is organic, indeed, resembling an
organism—a world sharply distinguished from that depicted by Epicurus and
Lucretius. One might rightly be critical of my glib characterization of the world
of Aristotle and Aquinas, but still recognize that that is a world radically
different from a world of undifferentiated atoms swerving in unpredictable
ways.
My
criticism: a bit of a discussion of this world within which, so to speak,
Christianity functions would have been an appropriate addition to Greenblatt’s
admirable book. In the course of such a discussion, the author might also have
been both more expansive and specific as to just how, in this way, the world
became modern.
_______________________
1I
may later read some of the many reviews of the book, but at this point I
haven’t looked at any of them.
Fyi: Stephen Greenblatt, The Swerve: How the World Became Modern. New York, W.W. Norton and Company, New York, 2011
2Epicurus:
241 BCE – 270; Lucretius: 99 BCE – 55.
No comments:
Post a Comment